First uncountable ordinalIn mathematics, the first uncountable ordinal, traditionally denoted by (or sometimes ), is the smallest ordinal number which, when viewed as a set, is uncountable (i.e. it does not have the same cardinality as the set of natural numbers). Equivalently, is the supremum (least upper bound) of all countable ordinals. In the standard von Neumann ordinal approach, an ordinal is a transitive set well-ordered by the membership relation , and iff . Thus, when considered as a set, the elements of are precisely the countable ordinals (including the finite ordinals ), of which there are uncountably many.[1] Like any ordinal number, is a well-ordered set. It is a limit ordinal (an ordinal with no immediate predecessor): there is no ordinal such that . The cardinality of the set is the first uncountable cardinal, denoted (aleph-one). The ordinal is therefore the initial ordinal of the cardinal (an initial ordinal is the least ordinal of a given cardinality). It is common in set theory to identify each infinite cardinal with its initial ordinal , so that as sets one may write . More generally, for any ordinal , denotes the initial ordinal of the cardinal . Under the continuum hypothesis (CH)—the statement that there is no set whose cardinality lies strictly between that of and that of —one has . In that case the cardinality of is also (the second beth number), the same cardinality as the set of real numbers.[2] The existence of does not require the full axiom of choice (AC). Indeed, for any set , the Hartogs number is the least ordinal that cannot be injected into ; taking yields an uncountable ordinal, which (by definition) is at least as large as . In particular, exists in ZF without AC. (Here, a set is countable if it is finite or countably infinite, i.e., in bijection with ; otherwise it is uncountable.) Topological propertiesFor ordinal intervals, we write for the set of all ordinals with , equipped with the order topology (see below). The space thus consists of all ordinals strictly less than , while includes the point as a top element. Any ordinal can be viewed as a topological space by giving it the order topology: a base is formed by open intervals together with initial segments of the form and, when the top element is present, final segments of the form . When considered with this topology, the space is denoted or as above. If the axiom of countable choice (CC) holds, every increasing -sequence (i.e., a sequence indexed by the natural numbers) in converges. Indeed, the pointwise union (which is the supremum in the ordinal order) of a countable set of countable ordinals is again a countable ordinal; therefore any increasing sequence has limit , which lies in . The space is sequentially compact (every sequence has a convergent subsequence) but not compact (there exist open covers with no finite subcover). Consequently, it is not metrizable (every compact metric space is sequentially compact and conversely, but a non-compact sequentially compact space cannot be metric). Nevertheless, is countably compact (every countable open cover admits a finite subcover; equivalently, every countably infinite subset has a limit point); since a space is compact iff it is both countably compact and Lindelöf (every open cover has a countable subcover), it follows that is not Lindelöf. In terms of axioms of countability, is first-countable (every point has a countable local base), but it is neither separable (it has no countable dense subset) nor second-countable (it has no countable base). By contrast, the space is compact (every open cover has a finite subcover) but not first-countable: the top point has cofinality (uncountable), so no countable neighborhood base can converge to it in the order topology. The ordinal is a standard building block for classical counterexamples in topology. The long line is obtained by taking the lexicographic order on and forming the associated order topology; it is locally like but not second-countable and not paracompact. The Tychonoff plank is the product space (with the product of order topologies), which exhibits further separability and compactness pathologies. See alsoReferences
Bibliography
|