Share to: share facebook share twitter share wa share telegram print page

Finite intersection property

In general topology, a branch of mathematics, a family of subsets of a set is said to have the finite intersection property (FIP) if any finite subfamily of has non-empty intersection. It has the strong finite intersection property (SFIP) if any finite subfamily has infinite intersection. Sets with the finite intersection property are also called centered systems and filter subbases.[1]

The finite intersection property can be used to reformulate topological compactness in terms of closed sets; this is its most prominent application. Other applications include proving that certain perfect sets are uncountable, and the construction of ultrafilters.

Definition

Let be a set and a family of subsets of (a subset of the power set of ). Then is said to have the finite intersection property if the intersection of a finite number of subsets from is always non-empty; it is said to have the strong finite intersection property if that intersection is always infinite.[1]

In the study of filters, the intersection of a family of sets is called its kernel, from much the same etymology as the sunflower. Families with empty kernel are called free; those with nonempty kernel, fixed.[2]

Examples and non-examples

The empty set cannot belong to any family with the finite intersection property.

If has a non-empty kernel, then it has the finite intersection property trivially. The converse is false in general (although it holds trivially when is finite). For example, the family of all cofinite subsets of a fixed infinite set — the Fréchet filter — has the finite intersection property, although its kernel is empty. More generally, any proper filter has the finite intersection property.

The finite intersection property is strictly stronger than requiring pairwise intersection to be non-empty, e.g., the family has non-empty pairwise intersections, but does not possess the finite intersection property. More generally, let be a natural number, let be a set with elements and let consists of those subsets of which contain all elements but one. Then the intersection of fewer than subsets from has non-empty intersection, but lacks the finite intersection property.

End-type constructions

If is a decreasing sequence of non-empty sets, then the family has the finite intersection property (and is even a π–system). If each is infinite, then admits the strong finite intersection property as well.

More generally, any family of non-empty sets which is totally ordered by inclusion has the finite intersection property, and any family of infinite sets which is totally ordered by inclusion has the strong finite intersection property. At the same time, the kernel may be empty: consider the family of subsets for .

"Generic" sets and properties

The family of all Borel subsets of with Lebesgue measure 1 has the finite intersection property, as does the family of comeagre sets.[3][4]

If and, for each positive integer , the subset is precisely all elements of having digit in the th decimal place, then any finite intersection of is non-empty — just take in those finitely many places and in the rest. But the intersection of for all is empty, since no element of has all zero digits.

Generated filters and topologies

If is a non-empty set, then the family has the FIP; this family is called the principal filter on generated by . The subset has the FIP for much the same reason: the kernels contain the non-empty set . If is an open interval, then the set is in fact equal to the kernels of or , and so is an element of each filter. But in general a filter's kernel need not be an element of the filter.

A proper filter has the finite intersection property. Every neighbourhood subbasis at a point in a topological space has the FIP, and the same is true of every neighbourhood basis and every neighbourhood filter at a point (because each is, in particular, also a neighbourhood subbasis).

Relationship to π-systems and filters

A π–system is a family of sets that is closed under finite intersections of one or more of its sets. For a family of sets , the family of sets which is all finite intersections of one or more sets from , is called the π–system generated by , because it is the smallest π–system having as a subset.

The upward closure of in is the set For any family , the finite intersection property is equivalent to any of the following:

  • The π–system generated by does not have the empty set as an element; that is,
  • The set has the finite intersection property.
  • The set is a (proper)[5] prefilter.
  • The family is a subset of some (proper) prefilter.[1]
  • The upward closure is a (proper) filter on . In this case, is called the filter on generated by , because it is the minimal (with respect to ) filter on that contains as a subset.
  • is a subset of some (proper)[5] filter.[1]

Applications

Compactness

The finite intersection property is useful in formulating an alternative definition of compactness:

TheoremA space is compact if and only if every family of closed subsets having the finite intersection property has non-empty intersection.[6][7]

This formulation of compactness is used in some proofs of Tychonoff's theorem.

Uncountability of perfect spaces

Another common application is to prove that the real numbers are uncountable.

TheoremLet be a non-empty compact Hausdorff space that satisfies the property that no one-point set is open. Then is uncountable.

All the conditions in the statement of the theorem are necessary:

  1. We cannot eliminate the Hausdorff condition; a countable set (with at least two points) with the indiscrete topology is compact, has more than one point, and satisfies the property that no one-point sets are open, but is not uncountable.
  2. We cannot eliminate the compactness condition, as the set of rational numbers shows.
  3. We cannot eliminate the condition that one-point sets cannot be open, as any finite space with the discrete topology shows.
Proof

We will show that if is non-empty and open, and if is a point of then there is a neighbourhood whose closure does not contain (' may or may not be in ). Choose different from (if then there must exist such a for otherwise would be an open one-point set; if this is possible since is non-empty). Then by the Hausdorff condition, choose disjoint neighbourhoods and of and respectively. Then will be a neighbourhood of contained in whose closure doesn't contain as desired.

Now suppose is a bijection, and let denote the image of Let be the first open set and choose a neighbourhood whose closure does not contain Secondly, choose a neighbourhood whose closure does not contain Continue this process whereby choosing a neighbourhood whose closure does not contain Then the collection satisfies the finite intersection property and hence the intersection of their closures is non-empty by the compactness of Therefore, there is a point in this intersection. No can belong to this intersection because does not belong to the closure of This means that is not equal to for all and is not surjective; a contradiction. Therefore, is uncountable.

CorollaryEvery closed interval with is uncountable. Therefore, is uncountable.

CorollaryEvery perfect, locally compact Hausdorff space is uncountable.

Proof

Let be a perfect, compact, Hausdorff space, then the theorem immediately implies that is uncountable. If is a perfect, locally compact Hausdorff space that is not compact, then the one-point compactification of is a perfect, compact Hausdorff space. Therefore, the one-point compactification of is uncountable. Since removing a point from an uncountable set still leaves an uncountable set, is uncountable as well.

Ultrafilters

Let be non-empty, having the finite intersection property. Then there exists an ultrafilter (in ) such that This result is known as the ultrafilter lemma.[8]

See also

References

Notes

Citations

  1. ^ a b c d Joshi 1983, pp. 242−248.
  2. ^ Dolecki & Mynard 2016, pp. 27–29, 33–35.
  3. ^ Bourbaki 1987, pp. 57–68.
  4. ^ Wilansky 2013, pp. 44–46.
  5. ^ a b A filter or prefilter on a set is proper or non-degenerate if it does not contain the empty set as an element. Like many − but not all − authors, this article will require non-degeneracy as part of the definitions of "prefilter" and "filter".
  6. ^ Munkres 2000, p. 169.
  7. ^ A space is compact iff any family of closed sets having fip has non-empty intersection at PlanetMath.
  8. ^ Csirmaz, László; Hajnal, András (1994), Matematikai logika (In Hungarian), Budapest: Eötvös Loránd University.

General sources

Prefix: a b c d e f g h i j k l m n o p q r s t u v w x y z 0 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9

Portal di Ensiklopedia Dunia

Kembali kehalaman sebelumnya